|
Liberal Education and Literature
by
Jim Kee
The notion of
a liberal arts education is an old one, but our shared understanding
of its meaning and significance today has not kept pace with the
reality of institutional structures in higher education. Somewhat
more than a century ago The Johns Hopkins University was founded
and became a prototype of the modern research university. Its departmental
structures reflected the fact that modern forms of knowledge and
inquiry are many and diverse and that individual disciplines do
not arrange themselves hierarchically in relationship to some foundational
discipline such as philosophy or rhetoric. During the twentieth
century liberal arts colleges have, of necessity, conformed themselves
more and more to the model of the research university—with the result
that our ability to articulate a compelling vision of the integrity
that might belong to liberal education has become more and more
attenuated.
What
are we to do about this? First, we must not, in the face of the
apparent fragmentation of knowledge, abandon the search for an integral
vision of liberal education. The "freedom" that "liberal"
education aims at demands as much. Secondly, nostalgia for some
real or imagined hierarchy of disciplines is not likely to lead
us to a vision of liberal education appropriate for today or tomorrow.
The differentiation of knowledge into more or less autonomous disciplines
has had its own necessities and has produced many salutary effects.
Whatever the vision of liberal education that we are capable of
today, its principles of unity will be all the richer if we honestly
address the multiplicities that belong to the contemporary college
or university. Thirdly, despite the relative degree of autonomy
that characterizes individual disciplines today, they still need
philosophical reflection. There are limit-situations encountered
in each discipline at which the discipline’s founding presuppositions
become questionable. At such places, a kind of thinking is called
for that is, properly speaking, philosophical, and a discipline
will not remain authentically responsive to its subject matter if
it evades this call. For this reason, philosophy itself cannot afford
the luxury of construing itself as just one discipline among others.
Philosophy has its special concerns, to be sure; but philosophy
will not remain true to its vocation if it withdraws from engaging
in dialogue with other disciplines when they encounter limit-situations.
In
these respects, then, my title indicates a desire to take up the
invitation to think about our common commitment to liberal education.
I do so, however, from the standpoint of one who is a practicing
literary critic. I assume that my discipline, too, operates in a
manner that grants it a degree of autonomy. Literary critics engage
in a variety of practices that cannot be subordinated to the requirements
of philosophy—or, for that matter, the requirements of history or
sociology. At the same time, literary critical practices lead us
to encounter limit-situations in which, to be responsive to our
subject matter, we must engage in a kind of thinking that is best
characterized as philosophical. One of these limit-situations is
encountered when we ask about the essential contributions literary
studies might make to a student’s liberal education. What I propose
to ask about here, therefore, is just that: Of all the matters that
belong to the "diffuse" discipline of literary criticism, what,
given the array of other disciplines practiced at a liberal arts
college, is the most essential contribution made by literary studies?
From
one point of view, literary studies has rarely been in a position
to offer more possible answers to this question. And that, of course,
is part of the challenge. The multiplicity that I earlier characterized
as belonging to the contemporary university in fact inhabits the
supposedly individual disciplines of that university. The challenge
goes so deep that many would, of course, object to the very point
of the question I have posed. Indeed, I’m willing to acknowledge
that literary criticism, left to itself, may today find little reason
to ask questions about what is most essential. But that is why I
want to tie my reflections to the issue of liberal education. In
our dealings with young people who come here hoping to realize for
themselves the promises of liberal education, we can’t afford the
luxury of considering questions about unity or integrity to be pointless
or meaningless. Looked at within the context of the lives of concrete
people who have been born and who will die, and who are here to
try and come to terms with what Wallace Stevens has called the "whole
shebang," questions concerning what is most essential are inescapable.
Priorities will be set—unconsciously, or on the basis of thoughtful
reflection.
Let
me explore the adequacy of some of the answers that have been given
since World War II. I will not and indeed could not seek to be comprehensive
here. In fact, I will make choices based in part on what I think
I know about the courses a typical English major takes before graduating.
We
have to start, I think, by considering that version of formalism
that came to be known as the "New Criticism," and, for purposes
of focus, I will refer primarily to the understanding of literary
studies common to such critics as Cleanth Brooks, in The Well-Wrought
Urn, and William Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley, in The Verbal
Icon.
The
principles of the New Criticism are in part responsible for making
literary studies available to multitudes of students since WWII.
Prior to the New Criticism, the dominant model of literary study
had been literary scholarship—a model, that is, which required one
to undergo years of specialized training in languages and philology
and literary history and textual scholarship in order to be, not
a literary critic, but a literary scholar. But the
New Criticism made the autonomous individual literary text the primary
object of study, and it developed principles for the critical evaluation
of that text which could be learned comparatively quickly. To this
day these emphases affect the way that we introduce students to
literary study in CRAW.
New
Critics were intensely aware that the natural sciences had emerged
as the most prestigious disciplines in the research university.
They therefore sought in part to establish literary criticism as
a discipline with a certain kind of scientific respectability. At
the same time, they saw in literature something vital that needed
to be preserved and defended against the imperialistic spirit of
scientific method. Their conceptions of poetry and the ways in which
a reader ought critically to evaluate poems reflect these competing
concerns.
On
the one hand, literary criticism needed to be made more objective
by being based upon evidence that was readily available in the public
domain. The primary evidence, New Critics argued, should be the
language of the poem—its syntax and semantics. The poem in turn
was conceived as an autonomous work of art with an essential form.
The New Critics’ emphasis upon publicly available evidence was intended
to differentiate their conception of literary criticism from a Romantically
inspired kind of criticism that located the essential being of a
poem in the consciousness of its creator. For the New Critics, literary
criticism could never be established as an objective discipline
if critics must somehow come to know the consciousness of the author.
What mattered was not the author’s intentional acts in creating
the poem but the form of the created object. And this, they argued,
is available for all to inspect. The standard of evidence that operates
in the New Criticism is almost positivistic—a fact which indicates
that the New Critics wanted literary criticism to measure up to
standards established by the positive sciences.
As
I said earlier, however, there is an "other hand" to New Critical
formalism. For New Critics literary criticism should also preserve
the vitality of the human spirit against scientific reduction. A
poem is a special kind of language, essentially different from the
language of science or of everyday communication. When a poet creates
a good poem, he or she brings into being a verbal icon. The verbal
icon has a thingly character. Unlike scientific propositions or
everyday discourse, the verbal icon’s words and syntax do not immediately
refer to something beyond themselves. They interact with each other
to create a work of art with a distinctive form. Based on the interplay
of parts and whole, the work has iconic significance. For the New
Critic, to understand a poem is to evaluate how its parts fit together
into a unified, organic whole. Content emerges from the appreciation
of form. Two criteria operate within the process of interpretation
and evaluation: unity and plenitude of meaning. The interpretation
of a part is acceptable if it can be made to fit into the form of
the whole. And the best poems—as well as the best readings of them—are
marked by a plenitude of meaning which is, potentially, infinite.
Cleanth
Brooks offers valuable insight into the basic assumptions that underlie
the New Criticism, and we do well to recognize these if we are to
appreciate why New Critical formalism remains so appealing to many
despite the loss of much of its authority within the discipline.
If we ask, "From whence is this conception of poetry derived? On
what is it founded?" Brooks provides the following response:
from a set of metaphysical assumptions associated with Romantics
such as Coleridge. A poem’s organic unity is an index of the kind
of unity effected by the creative imagination itself. That unity
reveals itself in the balance or reconcilement of opposite or discordant
qualities: of sameness with difference; of the general, with the
concrete; the idea, with the image; the individual, with the representative;
the sense of novelty and freshness, with old and familiar objects;
a more than usual state of emotion, with more than usual order.
The
passage, taken from Coleridge’s Biographia Literaria, is
a veritable catalog of the artistic ideals by which New Critics
distinguish good poems from bad ones. New Criticism values the paradoxical
unities achieved in poetry by the imagination because human experience
itself earnestly needs to be unified. In the depths of this vision
of poetry and experience is faith in what Gadamer has called an
"aesthetic metaphysics of individuality." Every properly realized
work of art is homologous with the totality of being as a whole.
Hence a great poem offers an experience of infinity. It endures
as a manifestation of eternity in time.
Before
addressing contemporary critiques of New Critical formalism, however,
I wish to attend to an alternative vision of literature that was
never entirely supplanted by it. In fact, this alternative even
combined with formalism at the level of commonsense practice to
define the discipline of literary studies in which most people earning
their Ph.D.s before 1980 were trained. I refer here to what now
needs to be called the old historicism or traditional historical
criticism.
In
contrast with New Criticism’s iconic conception of the literary
work of art, the old historicism conceived of literature rhetorically.
That is, it assumed that the literary work is a linguistic form
addressed by someone to an audience. To understand the work is to
grasp the author’s intention in writing it or to recognize how the
original audience would have understood it. For the old historicists
poetic language is not essentially different from other kinds of
language. In addition, poems can’t be treated as autonomous objects
because no verbal sequence, poetic or otherwise, can carry a determinate
meaning within itself. Even simple utterances can mean different
things in different contexts. For the old historicism, therefore,
the discipline of literary scholarship had to be founded upon attempts
to reconstruct the original context within which the work was written.
Old-style
historical criticism endured as a necessity of sorts within those
periods of literary history that pre-dated Romanticism. Here the
historical distance, one might even say alienation, between the
world of the contemporary reader and the horizon presumed by the
text seemed palpable, inescapable. To fail to attend to this problem
of historical distance would be to run the risk of merely seeing
one’s own prejudices in texts from the past. Traditional historical
criticism sought genuinely to listen to what was other in the text.
It felt an ethical obligation to do so. By so listening it hoped
to retrieve the past for the present, delighting in the past’s artistic
achievements and learning from its wisdom.
Like
formalism, the old historicism was more a practice than a highly
reflective theoretical position—in English and American literary
studies, as least, if not elsewhere. And despite the different manner
in which historicism conceived of textual meaning, it shared some
deeper assumptions with formalism that allowed the two to co-exist
with a certain complementarity. Both schools wanted to establish
literary studies as a respectable discipline within the university.
Both conceived of this challenge in terms of the need to seek objective
knowledge. Both thereby assumed the burdens of a whole array of
epistemological problems associated with the subject-object relationship.
In practice, the most successful New Critics were scholars who possessed
a historical sense that informed their readings of poems. Similarly,
the best traditional historicists attended to the form of the texts
they studied and appreciated their unique features. They thereby
resisted in all forms of historical criticism trying to assimilate
the individual text to typical patterns of meaning.
There
can be no doubt that traditional historical criticism and the literary
history that it produced has had many lasting effects upon literary
studies. But this enterprise, too, rested upon assumptions that
have today lost their authority for many. Let me touch upon a few
of these assumptions—again, primarily for the sake of making the
contemporary scene more intelligible. The old historicism turned
to context because the determinate meaning of the individual text
was not given in experience. But what is context? It is not given
in experience, either, and thus has to be constructed. The actual
practice of historical criticism indicates that, rather than allowing
the discipline to converge upon the true, determinate meaning of
individual texts, historical criticism often relocated the problem
of indeterminacy at the level of context. In the extreme, the problem
of context proliferates until one recognizes that the old historicist
project depends upon our ability to interpret history as a whole.
Unless we are Hegelians, that’s a problem. Moreover, because of
its rhetorical conception of the literary text, traditional historical
criticism tended to conceive history along the lines of intellectual
history or the history of ideas. It thus overlooked other ways of
conceiving history and literature’s relationship to it. Finally,
the requirement of wholeness led traditional historicists to emphasize
continuity in their construction of historical contexts. This emphasis
encouraged the formation of literary canons that excluded texts
which didn’t fit into the story being constructed.
As
I have mentioned, in England and America historical criticism was
always more a canon of practices than a well-articulated theoretical
movement. It never went through the agonizing theoretical quests
that were pursued by thinkers within the German hermeneutical tradition.
Nevertheless, the failure to reflect theoretically does not mean
that one is exempt from theoretical dilemmas. In my judgment traditional
historicism lost its authority because it was implicated in the
same set of Enlightenment and Romantic dilemmas that German philosophers
such as Dilthey wrestled with and whose character has become so
questionable in continental thought ever since Nietzsche (at least).
Anglo-American
literary studies today is a collection of diverse practices, many
of which were unimaginable just thirty years ago. I can envision
no return to greater uniformity in the near future. Nor do I see
a need to return to the kind of comparative uniformity that once
existed. Much differentiation has occurred within the modern university,
so I acknowledge the value of much that has emerged in literary
studies during the past thirty years. In order to tolerate or even
celebrate these differences, however, must we abandon the search
for ways to talk to one another across the abysses that now seem
to divide us? My own work is motivated by a faith that we not only
can but must keep searching for greater mutual understanding amid
our differences. We must do so out of responsibility to the subject
matter of our discipline. We must do so out of a sense of obligation
to each other. And we must do so for our students, who deserve a
major at the heart of their liberal arts education that affords
them more than an opportunity to be exposed to the many different
styles of literary criticism. Such a major they can hardly but experience
as a collection of idiosyncrasies. To engage in the search for genuine
conversation across the divides of the discipline is already to
belong together in a certain way.
This
is where we need help from our philosophically inclined colleagues.
After a fairly lengthy period of commonsense-based activity, so-called
literary "theory" has exploded upon the scene. At its best
it is, in my judgment, exhilarating, but at its worst it is willfully
self-justifying. Moreover, lots of practical literary criticism
proceeds on the basis of insufficiently understood motifs imported
from philosophy. It’s one thing to pick up the language of the philosophical
topoi. It’s another to have a genuine feel for what’s at
stake in the great traditions of philosophical debate that lie behind
these topoi. So, my dear philosophers, we need your help.
To
return now to my narrative: what happened to the old consensus?
Well, just about every major category of thought upon which its
world rested became questionable. The conception of the literary
text as an object; the conception of author and reader as subjects
capable of creating and receiving meaning; the conceptions of language;
the relation of subject, object, and language to history; the character
of history; the human relationship to the world—you name it, all
become questionable. Let me sketch briefly some of the major stages
in the process—not for the sake of evaluating the relative merits
of each but rather simply to register their successive shock values.
A
conception of language derived from structural linguistics called
into question the basic assumptions about language and meaning upon
which both formalism and the old historicism were founded. Structuralism
claimed to account for the production of meaning without conscious
intentionality, thereby reducing the author from a source of meaning
to a function of language. It accounted for linguistic meaning in
terms of a play of conventional differences that made formalism’s
autonomous work of art appear to be the product of a mystifying
desire. The individual text began to lose its objective boundaries
and became a more loosely defined site whose identity was a function
of differential relations within a web of inter-textuality. Finally,
structuralism made it appear that nature—the vaunted reference of
poetic mimesis at least since Aristotle—was not natural but social.
Nature, that is to say, is never given in immediacy; it is always
experienced as linguistically constructed.
A
variety of reader-response criticisms also began to explore what
had been concealed in the more traditional conceptions of texts
and reading. Stanley Fish, for example, indicted formalism as an
ideology that was positivist, holistic, and spatial. As such, he
sought to undermine the notion that a poem stands there as a finished
object in space with a meaning embedded in it, and that the reader’s
job is to grasp that meaning by figuring out how the object’s parts
form themselves into a whole. His critique aimed at clearing the
way for an appreciation of the reader’s active engagement over time
in a process of making sense of his or her experience as a reader.
Fish himself was criticized because his reader often looked like
the kind of privileged male who holds an endowed chair in English
at a prestigious university. But the way had been opened (and I
certainly don’t mean to give Fish all or even most of the credit
here) for considering the concrete reader’s subjective experiences
in reading. Others therefore have also explored reading from the
point of view of women, non-first-world women, different racial
and ethnic groups, gays and lesbians, members of different classes,
and so on.
As
more and more literary critics became convinced that the essential
foundations of formalism and the old historicism were in fact ideologically
determined, the way was also open for the wholesale entry into literary
studies of methods of critique derived from such thinkers as Marx
and Foucault, just to name two. The styles of literary criticism
which are today known by such names as the new historicism and cultural
studies draw their inspirations from these traditions of critique.
The traditional notion of the text as an object to be analyzed is
replaced by a conception of the text as a set of notations embedded
in a complex network of social practices. The task of literary criticism
is thus to analyze, not the components of a product, but the conditions
of a practice. Since these conditions are not likely to be given
overtly on the surface of texts, a depth-hermeneutic is required
that makes use of theoretical models—those drawn, for example, from
historical materialism. Influenced by Foucault’s notion of discourse—i.e.,
linguistic practices understood in the context of their relationships
to social institutions—the new historicism re-conceives history
as a field of discursive practices in which literature and criticism
make their own impact as political forces. They participate, as
it were, in the dialectic of historical materialism.
If
one were to survey the books and articles published by major university
presses and leading journals over the last dozen years, I think
one would conclude that cultural studies and the new historicism
have emerged, for now at least, as the dominant forms of literary
critical practice. Given this development, we ought to ask, "What
essential contribution to liberal education is made by literary
studies thus conceived?" The answer, it seems to me, would
have to be that it offers students the opportunity to engage in
certain powerful styles of critical thinking. They learn to be suspicious
of the past and its traditions and to work toward uncovering the
ideological distortions that permeated those traditions. It is worth
distinguishing between two different styles of critique here. One
stands squarely within the classic tradition of the modern Enlightenment
and is committed to the project of political liberation. In the
spirit of a thinker like Habermas, practitioners of this style believe
in the possibility of a critical reasoning that is not reducible
to one more set of powerful interests. They take their orientation
from a utopian vision of free and undistorted communication among
autonomous individuals. The other style of critique I would associate
with the name Foucault and, through him, Nietzsche. Its practitioners
are much less utopian in orientation—their suspicions extend even
to the projects of enlightened reason—and they are much more strategically
focused on particular historical situations.
I
cannot end this all too hasty survey of post-formalist developments
in literary studies without mentioning what is probably the most
notorious name to come upon the scene during the last thirty years:
Jacques Derrida. Before American literary criticism had had a chance
to come to terms with the structuralist critique of formalism, Derrida
arrived on the scene as a "post"-structuralist practicing something
known as deconstruction. It’s not much of a caricature to say that
deconstruction was received as having all the worst features of
structuralism-except that it also had a few of its own that made
it worse still! In many circles Derrida became known simply as a
nihilist—with little awareness of what that word had come to mean
in the thinking of Nietzsche or Heidegger. I would have to say that
Derrida is not much of a presence in literary studies today—and
this is deeply ironic, given the passions that his thought provoked
not long ago. I think this is so largely because deconstruction
was translated into American literary criticism simply as a technique
of reading, and it quickly became uninteresting as such. Derrida’s
work is in fact deeply and compellingly engaged with central problems
of thinking associated with names like Hegel, Nietzsche, Husserl,
and Heidegger, but American literary critics had neither the background
nor the inclination to read him as such. Consequently, the form
of life called deconstruction (if I might invoke Wittgenstein’s
notion here to distinguish deconstructive thinking from deconstructive
technique) was not well apprehended in American literary criticism.
I have come to think this unfortunate, but I do not have time on
this occasion to indicate why.
So
much for my survey. Let me conclude it simply by saying that the
gap between the formalists’ vision of literary study and the visions
of those who have come after is large; and regardless of what might
be happening at the most prestigious presses and journals, this
divide is having an extraordinary impact upon the character of the
undergraduate English major at most liberal arts colleges. We hardly
know how to talk to each other any more. And so, we tolerate the
differences until something important like a hiring decision brings
them to the fore.
It’s
time for me to offer my answer to the question I have posed. What
does literary studies today have to contribute to liberal education?
I must begin with a confession. I have all along tacitly been thinking
about these matters guided by my knowledge of the tradition of philosophical
hermeneutics associated with names such as Sehleiermacher, Dilthey,
Heidegger, Gadamer, Ricoeur, and, more recently, Gerald Bruns and
Donald Marshall. Although this tradition of thinking has had only
a slight impact upon American literary studies, I think it may offer
us resources for imagining literary studies in ways that not only
preserve what both formalists and cultural critics value but even
make sense of their strife. In part this is because hermeneutics
today is not primarily concerned with finding a method of interpretation.
Rather, hermeneutical reflection seeks to gain greater insight into
the conditions in which understanding occurs. It has a descriptive,
phenomenological side to it that I will seek to draw upon here.
The
principal starting point for a hermeneutical understanding of literary
studies today is Heidegger’s essay, "The Origin of the Work of Art."
Let me begin by suggesting how the hermeneutical thinking in this
essay might enable us to gather together some of the seemingly opposed
concerns that currently characterize literary studies. First, hermeneutics
valorizes the literary work of art just as formalism does. It acknowledges
the historical dimensions of the work in a manner that allows it
to address the concerns of the old historicism. It recognizes and
affirms the reader’s activities. It moves beyond the limited understandings
of language that characterize formalism and traditional historicism.
And it acknowledges in the work an historical play of blindness
as well as insight that may call for a critical hermeneutic of some
sort.
Beyond
these virtues, however, hermeneutics offers resources for thinking
that are simply not to be found in most of literary studies today.
It makes a profound break with the subject-object schema and the
epistemological problems that have plagued it. It thereby enables
us to think through the character of historical understanding more
adequately. More essentially still, it does not take the presence
of the world, or the work of art, or human beings, or society, or
history for granted. This is so because hermeneutics today emerges
from Heidegger’s retrieval of the pre-Socratic distinction between
das Sein and das Seiende—in English, between Being
and the individual being—a distinction that Heidegger names the
ontological difference. In the light of this difference, we are
able to provide a much more radical description of human understanding.
And we are able as well again to take up fundamental issues of poetics—a
topic that, oddly enough, has long been pushed to the margins of
literary studies.
At
the heart of the thinking in "The Origin of the Work of Art"
is the insight that the work of art is a happening, a work to be
accomplished, not a product finished once and for all. More pointedly,
the work of art is one of the ways in which truth happens. "Truth"
here does not name one of the transcendentals of traditional philosophy
but rather the way in which being unfolds, the process in which
things emerge into presence and withdraw from presence. Heidegger’s
habit of taking nouns and restoring them to the more primordial
verb forms that still inhabit them is a guide to his thinking here.
The work of art is just that: work to be accomplished, not an object
present at hand in the world. The work of art sets up a world,
holds open a world, within which the truth of some matter can emerge.
If that sounds remarkable, worthy of wonder, it is. Art, claims
Heidegger, is one of the "few essential ways" in which truth
happens. This is so, however, not because poetry is an essentially
different kind of language, as in the New Criticism. It is because
poetry realizes a possibility that is inherent in language as such.
The
work of art is carried out by its creator—of course. But this work
is also carried out by those who receive and take up the work—in
literary criticism we usually call these readers. In "The Origin
of the Work of Art" Heidegger calls them "preservers."
Just as a work "cannot be without being created," so what is
created "cannot itself come into being without those who preserve
it." Creating and preserving are different in many respects—poetics
is not identical with hermeneutics. Nevertheless, Heidegger’s language
describing what belongs most essentially to creating and preserving
is identical in one crucial respect. Of creation, he writes the
following: "to create is to let something emerge as a thing
that has been brought forth." Of preserving, he writes: preserving
the work means "letting the work be a work."
At the heart of both activities is a "letting be"—the German
here in both cases rests upon the verb lassen. On a later
occasion Heidegger would come to speak of this "letting be"
in language borrowed from the German mystical tradition, i.e., as
Gelassenheit. It is inextricably tied to an awareness and
acknowledgment of that which lets things emerge, of what in German
is heard as Es gibt—a phrase which translates into English,
unfortunately, only as "There is," not as "it gives."
This
"letting be," which is so essential to carrying out the work
of art for both poets and readers, is not a passivity but a doing
of the highest degree. It is characterized by uncommonly disciplined
attentiveness. In the finest poetic and hermeneutical accomplishments
it ordinarily rests upon superbly honed skills of the most mature
sort. But it is an activity that may also require something like
a self-emptying, even a suffering. To accomplish the work of art
we may have to "transform our accustomed ties to world and to earth
and henceforth to restrain all usual doing and prizing, knowing
and looking, in order to stay within the truth that is happening
in the work. Only the restraint of this staying lets what is created
be the work that it is."
Heidegger’s
call that we acknowledge the "letting be" which belongs to
the work of art may provide a way beyond one of the most contentious
points of debate between formalists, who place such emphasis upon
the poem as a whole, and those practitioners of newer styles of
literary criticism who accuse formalists of "holism." For formalists,
being accountable to the poem as a whole is a sine qua non
for disciplined literary criticism. It’s the only way to be sure
that your efforts are carrying you beyond yourself and an uncritical
enslavement to your prejudices. For more recent critics, an insistence
upon the unity of the poem can make one complicit in the poem’s
ideological project. The demand for unity is intended to enforce
hierarchies and conceal differences. There may be truth to this
suspicion. From a formalist’s point of view, however, failure to
respect the poem as a whole makes it too easy for cultural critics
to treat poems as raw materials for producing allegorical readings.
From
the perspective provided by "The Origin of the Work of Art,"
the formalist’s demand for unity has a certain naïve character
to it. It is flawed by the assumption that the poem stands there
fully present as a completed object that carries its meaning within
it. In spite of this naïveté, however, formalists’ hearts
are in the right place. They seek to be accountable to the truth
of the poem’s subject matter as these emerge in carrying out the
work of art. This truth never stands forth, however, in the mode
of full presence. What emerges into presence always does so on the
basis of a concealment. In the language of Heidegger’s essay, truth
in the work of art happens as a strife between world and earth,
between that which sets up a clearing and that upon which it must
stand - called here the earth, that which shelters and conceals.
The
perspective provided by "The Origin of the Work of Art" also
offers some support to those whose work makes use of a critical,
suspicious hermeneutic. Their refusal to accept the formalists’
demand for unity appears based upon a justifiable suspicion of the
formalists’ desire for unity conceived as a presence. In addition,
the character of truth’s happening as both disclosure and concealment
helps to illuminate why ideological distortions can occur. But that
said, we must ask: Can we simply dismiss with all concern for unity?
Or is there a desire for unity concealed even in the practice of
critical hermeneutics?
Heidegger’s
account of the work of art as the truth that happens in the strife
between world and earth has analogies with the ancient insight that
thinking unfolds between the One and the Many, between unity and
indeterminacy. In the Philebus Plato cautions against those
who would arrive at the One or the Many too quickly out of a desire
to escape the burdens of being in the in-between. If the formalists
have assumed Oneness too quickly, their postmodern critics, I fear,
have arrived too quickly at multiplicity. And when we arrive at
the Many too quickly, we often do so by unwittingly thinking from
a standpoint that presumes unity. (Think here, for example, of the
monolithic ideological character of some of the simpler expressions
of multiculturalism.) A critical hermeneutic carried out relentlessly
rests upon the presumed unity of the critical consciousness that
carries out the critique. Such a consciousness refuses to risk the
self-emptying, the internal multiplicity even, that the work of
art can call for. It thus cannot engage in the work of letting be.
How
do we know if we are engaging in this work of letting be? I don’t
think we can know for sure, and this may be one of the reasons why
we return over and over again to the greatest works of art and try
to carry out the work more responsively. But we are not totally
ignorant, either. We may have an indication that we are "letting
the work be" when we are aware of what is concealed in the
work as concealed. That is, we recognize the concealment
and let it be as concealment. This awareness, in my judgment, is
a sign that we are acknowledging the work’s authenticity, its ownness,
the essential unfolding of its historical identity, and not just
pursuing the advancement of our own projects.
To
illustrate the character of this "letting be" more concretely,
I would like to look briefly at a poem by Elizabeth Bishop called
"The Fish"—a poem which is probably known to many of you. I
suggest we read the poem as a parable of "letting be." As we
go through the poem, we take note of the active verbs used by the
speaker: "I caught, I thought, I looked, I admired, I saw, I stared
and stared, I let go." These actions, I wish to argue, all
belong to the action of letting be that the speaker explores in
the poem.
At
the very moment that the fish’s essential being stands most fully
revealed, it withdraws into the brilliance of the symbol that discloses
the truth of its being: the rainbow. In that symbol the poem articulates
the speaker’s awareness of the mystery concealed in the revelation
of the fish’s being. And so, she lets the fish go. This is what
I mean when I say that an awareness of the concealed as concealed
may be a crucial indication that we are indeed engaged in the disciplined
labor of letting the work of art be.
I
have tried to present an argument that is inclusive in spirit—that
is open to discovering how today’s diverse modes of literary critical
practice might, in the light of philosophical hermeneutics, be valued
for the different contributions they make even as they are understood
as belonging together in some intelligible way. I believe, however,
that there is one question implicit in what I have said that does
confront us with an either/or choice. The question concerns what
Paul Ricoeur calls the fundamental gesture of thinking, and it goes
like this: Is this gesture one of acknowledgment—acknowledgment
of the mysterious conditions between becoming and perishing, birth
and death, in which all human understanding happens? Or is it, in
the last analysis, a critical gesture, relentlessly and repeatedly
on guard against forms of false consciousness?
I
believe the fundamental gesture of thinking is this gesture of acknowledgment.
And I think that the future value of literary studies within liberal
education will depend upon a renewed appreciation of this gesture.
At its best literary studies prepares students to participate in
one of the few essential ways in which truth happens: the work of
art. More than many other disciplines in this scientifically and
technologically driven age, it can offer students an opportunity
to engage in a kind of thinking that is not just critical but also
humble, hopeful, and even thankful. It can lead them to recognize
the happening of the world - and to wonder at the mystery that this
should be so.
|
|