|
Eurocentrism and Pluralism
by
Joseph P. Lawrence
The
thesis I would like to argue is that the "new," purportedly more
radical, forms of pluralism that have arisen in the latter half
of the 20th century are decisively less pluralistic than
the ancient forms of pluralism that lie at the heart of Western
culture. This observation has two interesting consequences. The
first one is profoundly distressing: the cultural battles that are
currently being waged against "ethnocentrism" tend themselves to
contribute to its perpetuation. Liberalism has indeed developed,
as is most apparent within the confines of the university, a fascistic
vanguard. The second observation is a more hopeful one: a reappropriation
of what lies at the heart of our culture could provide a way out
of our dilemma.
I
have referred intentionally to a plurality of pluralisms. What this
could mean with regard to the cultural heritage of the West can
be made quickly apparent. Two separate, though mysteriously related,
events have given shape to that culture. The first can be evoked
with the name of Plato and represents the outcome of the battle
between the philosophers and the poets, a battle which the philosophers
won decisively enough that Western culture is distinguished by its
commitment to science and rationality. The other event I have in
mind is the astonishing retreat of tribal religion in the face of
Christianity’s claim to worldwide legitimacy.
Both
of these events can be interpreted as victories for pluralism. Consider,
for instance, that strange Christian command "love thy enemy," which
has as its philosophical correlate the idea that we must always
strive to listen to our opponent’s argument. Or consider the striking
emphasis placed upon the individual in both Aristotelian and Christian
metaphysics.
This
is, of course, not the whole story. One can certainly argue that
power and dogmatism rather than reason and toleration represent
the true spirit of Europe and the West. The subordination of reason
to power is in fact made explicit in the contemporary age of technology:
the reduction of nature and to a large extent of human beings themselves
to the status of manipulable resources for the benefit of those
with power has had devastating effects, the mutilation of nature,
the industrialization of culture, and the impoverishment of the
third world. From Heidegger to Derrida to radical feminism, it has
become customary to blame all of this on a rational metaphysics
that eradicates difference for the sake of comprehending universal
forms. The theoretical project of understanding the world, we are
told, serves to mask a deeper and more problematic practical aim:
the world is not so much to be understood as a mechanical system
as to be transformed into one. Thus science, according to Heidegger,
is always already technological in nature. The construction, for
instance, allegedly for theoretical purposes, of a model of the
DNA molecule is the prelude to genetic engineering: the industrialization
of the life process itself, an industrialization that must ultimately
serve the interests of those with power.
The
argument, so far as it goes, seems to be fully correct. The metaphysical
identification of true reality with intelligible structure did in
fact, via the Christian doctrine of creation, i.e., the denial of
the self-sufficiency of nature, and the reduction of intelligibility
to the Cartesian cogito, prepare the way for the industrial age.
The idea of creation subordinated nature (as primordial chaos) to
the will of God. With the grandiose insistence of 17th
century science that the will of God can be fathomed (by unveiling
the laws of nature), man himself assumed the posture of mastery.
Nature, which itself always tends to wilderness (the threatening
and fear-evoking), is to be tamed and systematically exploited.
The very ground of "otherness" is thereby systematically eradicated.
This
is a historical "fact" that I am not about to deny. I believe, however,
that this thought structure, the metaphysics of modernity, arose
only through the oblivion of the more fundamental metaphysical insight
that the intelligibility of what is derives from a deeper source
which, taken in itself, is incomprehensible. This is what Plato
called "the Good," locating it "above both knowledge and being"
and what Christianity understood as Divine Love: the ecstatic, purely
other-related structure of true Being. The recognition of this incomprehensibility
is what alone assures the openness of the Western spirit, just as
parallel insights have assured the openness of those other non-tribal,
globally-oriented, religious cultures such as Hinduism and Buddhism.
I
With
that, then, as my introduction, let me take up the issue at hand.
When I speak of the "New Pluralism" I am referring above all to
the rejection of philosophical "foundationalism" and the consequent
insistence that one must think in terms of "language games," "conceptual
frameworks," "semantic schemata," "provisional paradigms," "rhetorical
tropes," and the like. It is this theoretical assertion that we
can never advance beyond a particular perspective on the truth that
motivates the political plea that we try to accommodate as many
perspectives as possible. The result, of course, is the broad coalition
of marginalized perspectives, the "black" perspective, the "woman’s"
perspective, sundry "ethnic" perspectives, the "gay" perspective,
and so forth, that are loosely allied under the slogan of "post-modernity"
and represent for political conservatives the phantom of left-wing
fascism, the purveyors of the "politically correct." By regarding
itself as post-modern, this new pluralism understands itself as
providing a radical alternative to that more conventional liberalism
that grew out of the 18th century Enlightenment, a liberalism
that, according to the new pluralists, perniciously subordinated
its ideal of toleration to the rule of reason, the very principle
which facilitated the uncanny leveling of cultural differences that
has accompanied the globalization of the West. Because the pride
of the marginalized is precisely their lack of complicity in this
grotesque imperialism, my attempt here to assert that their intellectual
advocates are themselves agents of that imperialism may likely be
construed as offensive. Like virtually all philosophers before me,
and despite any claim I might make to speak as an "outsider," I
will appear to be little more than a defender of the prevailing
system, seemingly oblivious to what thinkers like Marx knew so well,
that, in a world defined by glaring injustices, the goal must not
be to understand the world, but to change it.
Now
instead of focusing on the hypocrisy of the activist qua
intellectual, I want to call attention to what should be readily
apparent: this form of activism is itself identical with modernism,
which is also to say, it is European to the core. The distance from
Hobbes to Marx or even to Foucault is not terribly great; one has
only to realize that the natural state of anarchy is not fully eradicated
by the formation of the state: it exists implicitly in the tensions
between classes and explicitly in the anarchy among nations that
to this day, new world order or not, refuse to sacrifice their own
sovereignty for the good of the whole. The goal of establishing
a rational order by renouncing upon power undergoes, it is true,
a significant revision within post-modernism: it is replaced by
the goal of empowering those without power. But precisely insofar
as the modern conception of reason is grounded in the understanding
that reason is always established rather than given, that is to
say, that it is essentially a crystallization of power, the apparent
difference vanishes, and the post-modern project discloses itself
as a radicalization of the modern imperative, to construct a better
world than the one we have inherited. The enormous emphasis on reconstructing
reality involves the denial of the relevance of the natural order,
a denial that is bought at a tremendous cost: not only does it displace
metaphysics by ideology, but it binds us more fully than ever into
the machinery of the technological, and ultimately dissolves any
possible standard by which that machinery might be directed, or
left to anything but its own devices.
What
is involved here can be seen in contemporary feminism, which became
radical when it denied its own indebtedness to the European quest
for universality. By understanding the word "men" in "all men are
created equal" as gender exclusive, it eradicated the possibility
of a theoretical justification of the struggle for gender inclusivity.
What we are left with is the appearance of a purely political struggle,
whereby the disempowered, motivated solely by the hope of realizing
their own desires, seek power. The problem is that what is simply
denied, that feminism is a product of the long history of Western
rationality, now exerts its influence from behind, that is, blindly.
The equation, for instance, of gender with a culturally rather than
a naturally inscribed difference reduces one of the grounds of personhood
itself to the status of something manipulable and thus controllable.
In a similar way, the program of language reform, which lies at
the heart of the feminist project, presupposes a denial of the natural
basis of language, upon which alone cultural differences are ultimately
grounded. The technological eradication of otherness can proceed
unimpeded. For no culture can now be regarded as anything but a
constellation of arbitrary conventions, many of which will simply
have to be reconstituted.
If
Japanese culture, for instance, assigns to women a subordinate status,
feminism will hardly be able to acknowledge its right to continue
to do so. If the Japanese language embodies different grammatical
forms to be used by men and women, then that too will have to be
changed. Similarly the practice by many Middle Eastern and African
societies of female circumcision, the use in others of amniocentesis
to facilitate the abortion of female fetuses, the total exclusion
of women from one rite or the other, none of this will be excused
by feminism in the name of resisting ethnocentrism - nor, of course,
should it be. But because the very idea of a transcultural standard
has been rejected as an imposition of a patriarchal culture, the
only possible justification for fighting these injustices has to
be construed in culturally immanent terms: the world is to be made
Western, for no better reason than that we like the way things are
done in the West. Radical feminism presents itself as a new tribalism.
In
order to escape the charge that, in the dominant Western male mode,
I am engaging in an abstract form of discourse that leaves myself
removed and uncommitted, I will offer as my next example something
from my own experience. I grew up in a pocket of Appalachian culture
in rural Kentucky that was effectively destroyed by any number of
forces, but certainly in part by the 1960’s War on Poverty. Hillside
shacks without plumbing, sometimes without wooden floors, have given
way to trailers and, even more, to brick or concrete housing projects
in the towns. A diet of wild greens, of squirrel and possum and
even blackbird soups and pies, has been supplanted by various mass
produced starches. Homemade whiskey has given way to beer. Homemade
music has largely disappeared. A visionary perspective rooted in
the lay of the land and the shape of the hills has given way to
the new universalized perspective afforded by television. Some of
the change can be regarded as an improvement, some of it as a tragic
loss. In any event, the world of my childhood has disappeared almost
completely - and by forces that are in no way curbed by the appearance
in the academy of a new pluralism.
To
bemoan the loss of that world would, of course, be romanticism:
and within the academy romanticism counts as an error, almost regardless
of one’s political perspective. From the vantage point of the new
pluralism, the essential error would lie in the failure to acknowledge
how utterly arbitrary all of the cultural "differences" were, which,
taken together, inscribed the "text" of that lost Kentucky world
I could so sentimentally evoke. But from my perspective, there was
strikingly little about those differences that was arbitrary: it
was a world, not a text at all, and it was etched into and indeed
by the land itself. What might strike the outsider as quaint convention
was to the insider not convention at all, but often simple necessity,
a necessity borne out of what it took to survive in that time and
place. One ate blackbirds not because it was quaint to do so, but
because one was hungry and blackbirds were to be had. If the women
served the men dinner and then ate afterwards themselves, this was
doubtlessly deplorable in some way, but just as rooted in a set
of conditions that even an academic should try to respect.
While
it is commendable that such pictures, and some that are considerably
more exotic than the one I have so briefly sketched, are preserved
and catalogued by students of culture, it should be clear that this
is essentially a museum activity. Their scholarly investigation
already presumes that the life forms themselves are past: to speak
of what can be "learned" from them is disingenuous and patronizing.
The real effect of the "new pluralistic" appropriation of such forms
is that they are literally torn out of the ground that gave rise
to and sustained them. They are held for restructuring and, if possible,
absorption into the world that matters, something like the "women
of color" who, as the Calcutta-born feminist deconstructionist Gayatri
Spivak points out, are so assiduously sought after for inclusion,
after their proper cleansing and "education," in the middle class
world of academe. And if, as is almost universally the case, they
cannot be thus "saved," their lives are chronicled for the lessons
they might hold for us or, what is far worse, for their entertainment
value.
Intellectual
honesty, I believe, should force us to realize that there may in
fact be something patronizing about that procedure, which calls
upon marginalized voices to represent their exotic perspectives
so that we white middle-class European-Americans might remain true
to the specifically Western ideal of broadening our perspectives
beyond their Eurocentric bias. Will you, we effectively ask the
marginalized, limit yourselves intellectually in order to help set
us free. I hope this point can be taken seriously. I am not denying
that simple justice may demand affirmative hiring procedures. I
am asking, however, that we try to understand those Clarence Thomas
types who refuse to play the roles that are assigned to them. To
dismiss them as a priori inauthentic is to forget the authenticity
of the drive for transcendence and freedom that can catapult one
far from one’s origins. The very earnestness with which we ourselves
endeavor to transcend our own race, gender, and class determined
biases, should make us rebel at the notion that intellectuals are
needed who, for our sakes, will "represent" rather than expand their
own perspectives.
We
might also pause and consider the violence we exercise, when we
tear works out of their own linguistic and cultural contexts in
order to translate them into European languages and incorporate
them, for our own edification, into world literature textbooks -
or what happens when we then submit them to discussions guided by
the assumption that the problems they depict somehow overlap with
our own problems. I recall the irritation expressed by some of my
Japanese friends over the way, in the United States, "Buddhism"
is taught in the framework of "oriental philosophy" courses. They
pointed out that in Japan itself, philosophy is taught as a peculiarly
Western tradition that is separated by an abyss from their own cultural
forms. To understand Buddhism as philosophy is to deny its own integral
nature and to subsume it under categories utterly foreign to it.
In the same vein, I remember the comment made by the Japanese philosopher
Tezuka in the 1950’s that it is impossible to grasp anything Japanese
through the medium of movies, for movies are themselves a peculiarly
Western mode of objectifying and thereby Europeanizing whatever
they depict. Movies are, after all, rife with images. The Japanese
stage, in contrast, is empty of all props. The emptiness of that
stage belongs to the unique essence of Japanese culture. If we can
listen to what these Japanese voices are saying, we have to acknowledge
the fact that because cross-cultural studies rely upon European
media, they may very well accomplish precisely the opposite of what
they intend to accomplish. We have a very European need to respect
differences, but seem to be tragically ensnared in the dialectic
of European imperialism.
I
do not want to question anyone’s motives and intentions. In the
majority of cases, the investigator turns to a foreign culture,
motivated by the explicit recognition of the deficiencies of our
own culture. But insofar as his concern will be one of translation,
he will be caught fast: what is "other" gets expressed in our own
terms. While a form of knowing does indeed exist that does not make
what is known immanent to the knower, it is an exceedingly difficult
form to perfect, and one whose very possibility clashes with the
deepest presuppositions of the new pluralism.
I
want now to turn my attention to this alternative form of knowing.
I do not present it as anything new. It is in fact the oldest of
the old. Its spirit is more profoundly pluralistic than is the spiritlessness
of the new pluralism. Its foundation lies deeper than any arbitrary
conceptual or linguistic scheme: ultimately it is rooted in nature
itself, not in the objectified nature studied by the contemporary
sciences, but in that inscrutable nature that, ever anew, draws
forth from darkness the possibility of life.
II
In
order to effectively distinguish that oldest of pluralisms from
the new, I must comment quickly upon a key passage in Jacques Derrida’s
essay on Plato’s dialogue, the Phaedrus. What I find remarkable
about Derrida’s essay is first of all that he quite correctly refrains
from interpreting Plato as a Platonist, that is, as the inventor
of dogmatic metaphysical "universalism." He understands that Plato
wrote dialogues because he made no claim to possess absolute knowledge
- and he understands that these dialogues require no deconstructive
ploy to have their profound ambiguities laid bare. In other words,
Derrida concedes throughout his essay the astonishingly "pluralistic"
implications of Plato’s Phaedrus. Yet he takes issue with
the fact that Plato’s pluralism wants to anchor itself in the depths
of the "heart," the forgotten regions of the soul. He rejects the
idea that the highest form of writing must be written into the soul
itself, that the "lived" word, the spirited word, should be privileged
above words written in a text.
Such
Platonic writing is, according to Derrida, at best "a dis-covering,
a writing of aletheia" (or truth) and thus capable of "sustaining
itself in living dialogue, capable most of all of properly teaching
the true, as it is already constituted." Derrida balks above all
at this "already," and the entire image of midwifery, of philosophy
as a dialogue that enables us to give birth to the wisdom buried
deeply within our hearts. Over against this, Derrida unfolds the
structuralist conception that written words themselves give rise
to other written words, that texts generate new texts. Linguistic
signs he regards not as expressions of an inner spirit, but as arbitrary
marks that are granted a provisional kind of meaning by virtue of
the relationships they have with other equally arbitrary marks.
Writing, for Derrida, is the generation of meaning, not its discovery.
By rejecting the notion that there is a meaning to be discovered,
he effectively denies the reality of nature, of the always "already
was" that, in its fullness, seeks articulation in the understanding.
To maintain meaning in its provisional fluidity, Derrida resorts
to his constant deconstructions. This would be commendable if done
in the name of a purification of the soul that would prepare it
for a Divine inscription, but, by declaring that words can never
mean anything except more words, Derrida trades that potential purification,
that potential "silencing," for its opposite, the garrulousness
of the modern theoretician who is afraid ever to stop talking.
My
purpose here is not to provide any kind of commentary on texts of
Derrida or of Plato. But I do want to call attention to something
that I find enormously ironic. Derrida identifies his rejection
of "meaning in nature" with a rejection of the father, and the father’s
claim to authority. If the father, slumbering wisdom of nature,
knows more than I do, he may assert his "authority." He may attempt
to subjugate me by insisting upon the obscurity of the good, which
he thereby holds above me. Through his attempt to disinflate such
a hierarchical relationship, Derrida reveals himself as a child
of the European Enlightenment, seeking to free himself and others
by claiming equal access to truth, insofar as truth can still be
said to exist. In other words, Derrida, the last great "debunker"
of the Platonic conception of universality, turns out in one way
to be more Platonic than Plato. For he effectively denies the very
earth upon which we stand and delivers us before the field of what
he calls differance, externally marked forms that both negate
and replicate themselves into infinity; he delivers us, in other
words, before a realm of "pure form," a realm that even Plato -
or rather precisely Plato - denied could ever be fully ours.
The
reason Plato himself refrained from fully embracing his own "theory
of forms" was that he realized the impossibility of thinking away
the earth, the ground of our erotic rather than purely intellectual
constitutions. His battle against the sophists, the "relativists"
or "deconstructionists" of his own time, was carried out not in
the name of a dogmatic and difference-obliterating super Reason,
but rather in the name of our erotic natures. This point, by the
way, will please contemporary political conservatives as little
as it will please the new pluralists. The opposition is not one
between the modern principle of spontaneity and the classical principle
of nature as a reservoir of fixed truths. For nature, as thought
by the ancients, was the source of spontaneity, not its limit. It
is impossible to read Plato’s "erotic" dialogues in any other way.
Plato himself always remained true to the Socratic dictum that the
highest knowledge we human beings can attain is the knowledge of
our finitude, the awareness f how painfully little we can really
know. Within this dictum we can find the distinction between the
two forms of knowledge that I referred to earlier. The knowledge
that is disclaimed is the knowledge that would deliver the determinate
and thus intelligible structure of what is over to our minds, the
knowledge that would enable us to assume "command" over the world.
It is a knowledge that we often want to claim as our own on the
basis of the sophistic assertion that we ourselves create the order
of the world, an assertion that completes itself, paradoxically
perhaps, simultaneously in modern technology and the new "post-modern"
pluralism, we find so often discussed today. Yet Plato was aware
of what we so frequently forget; even the models that we ourselves
construct are based ultimately on principles and methods that we
did not invent, but had given to us. Given not, as conservatives
would have it, by the unchanging luminosity of self-evident truth,
but given instead out of an origin that cannot be rendered intelligible
and thereby made our own, given, that is to say, as a "gift." What
is to be "dis-covered" through that other alternative form of knowledge,
which Plato tells us is the closest that we humans can ever come
to wisdom, is first and foremost our own essential poverty of spirit
and, in unpredictable and divine moments, that gratuitous inflow
of meaning that is not ours by "right," but, to use Plato’s word,
by Love.
True
knowledge does not disclose the world as an articulation of our
own inborn or spontaneously constructed rationality. Let us be thankful
for that, for if this were true knowledge, then its realization
would be an awakening into solipsism. We would find ourselves utterly
alone. Not alone in an alien world, but, what is infinitely worse,
alone in ourselves. True knowledge is instead ecstatic in structure,
realized only as a gift of our constant dying. Spirit lives not
through the self-assertion of the Word, but through its Calvary,
its death and surrender, theologically construed, to the authority
of the invisible Father; philosophically construed, to the nurturing
womb of earth, the eternal Mother.
I
touch here the dimension of myth. This is precisely where Derrida
fails most dramatically in his reading of Plato’s Phaedrus.
He asserts that Plato is as indifferent to myth itself as to sophistic
deconstructions of mythical claims, that he simply sets myth aside
in order to carry out the rational project of "understanding himself."
What he ignores thereby is that in order to understand the self,
for Plato the soul, the Phaedrus makes it clear that only
myth will suffice. The entire central part of Plato’s dialogue is
in fact devoted to the elaboration of such a mythical account. Moreover,
this is the case precisely because Plato does not understand the
origin of the word in a patriarchal way as the subjugation of matter
by pure form, but instead he understands the origin itself as earth-bound,
as Eros. The gods themselves he does not identify with form; he
depicts them as journeying forth towards the ecstatic vision of
form from a home to which they always return, the earth. Eros itself,
and that, by the way, is to say the soul itself, is, Plato emphasizes
again and again, androgynous; it incorporates the female as fully
as the male.
Derrida’s
mistake is also the mistake of a radical feminism like that of Mary
Daly, which creates the myth of a purely male-centered hierarchy
in order to debunk it in the name of the liberated. It expels the
feminine from the heart of the European essence in order to reject
that essence for its bias. The irony is also visible here. For in
thus expelling the feminine from thought itself, feminism, with
rare exceptions like Camille Paglia, binds itself into the genuinely
patriarchal form of the non-philosophical, that is to say, non-erotic
European Enlightenment. It turns its back on nature and lauds the
liberated self as the autonomous agent of cultural creation.
The
new pluralism is a pluralism without roots, without that erotic
determinacy that is the true source of the staggering multiplicity
of cultural meaning. It is Eurocentric insofar as it, through its
denial of metaphysics, dispenses with the depth dimension of reality
and delivers us over to a flood of information about competing cultural
practices. It overlooks the fact that each of those different cultures
is alive only to the degree that it is rooted in whatever reflective
mode it has been granted for savoring and recollecting the depth
dimension itself. The implicit anti-intellectualism of the new pluralism
is therefore its greatest weakness. We can’t deny the legitimacy
of trying to think as profoundly and comprehensively as possible
and then expect to understand anything essential about other cultures,
cultures that are themselves invariably grounded in a thinking that
is profound and comprehensive. In other words, the denial of metaphysics
is the denial of culture itself, its systematic reduction to exteriority.
To
complete my argument, I shall very briefly turn from the "erotic"
Plato to the more systematic Aristotle. While recognizing that Aristotle
already betrays something of the narrow rationalism of the tradition
that follows, he is still important to my theme, insofar as his
identification of substance with concrete individuals represents
the origin of traditional forms of Western pluralism. It is a form
of pluralism that grew directly out of Aristotle’s quest for unity.
That quest was completed in his Metaphysics, a work that
has at its heart the idea that, to understand reality, one needs
recourse not to one, but to four different kinds of principles.
An understanding of this doctrine makes it clear that Aristotle
accommodated the fundamental metaphysical alternatives by reducing
them to separate principles that complement, rather than exclude
one another. While purely mechanical systems can only be understood
via efficient causality, organic systems can be understood either
mechanically or teleologically. This idea of complementary principles
is nothing foreign to the thinking of science; one thinks, for instance,
of the reconciliation through complementarity of classical, quantum,
and relativistic physics.
Without
developing this idea, I want to suggest that a similar complementarity
can be understood to lie behind the dramatic division between the
"erotic" and the "rational" that has torn the modern academy into
the competing and apparently mutually exclusive worlds of the "arts"
and the "sciences." The same sun both in fact "rises" and "only
appears" to rise as the earth turns. One perspective is truer to
the phenomenon, while the other affords a simpler way of modeling
the motions of the other planets. Both perspectives in fact have
a claim to truth. An understanding of this complementarity is, however,
because it is a complementarity of foundational perspective, impossible
for that pluralism which rejects a priori any form of foundational
thinking.
After
establishing this, I want to conclude by suggesting that the different
complementary worldviews do, however, follow one another in a definite
sequence. The "rising" sun is both logically and ontologically prior
to the sun that appears to rise. The reality of its rising forth
displays itself only for those who are willing to set aside all
"schematizing perspectives" in order simply to see. Because of the
sheer primacy of what there unfolds, all desire to know and order
will be silenced. Into this pure seeing, the vision of the open
mind, the inexplicable and the Divine will pour itself. Enraptured,
let us give ourselves over to that event until, like Socrates, we
might say our prayer to Apollo and then quietly retreat to attend
our private affairs.
|
|